Start Etyka psychologiczna - artykuł - Pomoc psychologiczna czy psychoterapia(1), Psychologia, Pomoc psychologiczna Etiologiczna klasyfikacja cukrzycy, Pielęgniarstwo, Interna i pielęgniarstwo internistyczne, Diabetologia, Artykuły ewangelizacja(1), Dokumenty (w tym Dokumenty Kościoła), Artykuły teologiczne, o ewangelizacji znalezione w internecie Ewangelie - omówienie, Artykuły różne, biblia i nie biblia Evaluation of ethanol-chlorhexidine gluconate scrub surgical, Artykuły z zakresu dezynfekcji, Dezynfekcja - rodzaje baz, środków Evidence for selectivity of absorption of volatile organic, Artykuły naukowe, SPME i HS-SPME EVALUAT REVIT HAOUSING, Architektura Krajobrazu, Artykuły różne - rewitalizacja, planowanie, krajobraz Europa%20w%201244%20roku, Wczesne, Wikingowie, PDF, artykuły o wikingach Evelyne Pieiller - Koniec świata czy pewnego świata, Artykuły prasowe Evans, Angielskie [EN](4)(2) |
Evolution, Filozofia, Filozofia - Artykuły[ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]Philosophy of Science Association Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism Author(s): Elliott Sober Source: Philosophy of Science, Vol. 47, No. 3 (Sep., 1980), pp. 350-383 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association Stable URL: Accessed: 26/10/2008 11:26 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Philosophy of Science Association and The University of Chicago Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy of Science. EVOLUTION, POPULATION THINKING, AND ESSENTIALISM* ELLIOTT SOBERt University of Wisconsin-Madison Ernst Mayr has argued that Darwinian theory discredited essentialist modes of thought and replaced them with what he has called "population thinking". In this paper, I characterize essentialism as embodying a certain conception of how variation in nature is to be explained, and show how this conception was undermined by evolutionary theory. The Darwinian doctrine of evolution- ary gradualism makes it impossible to say exactly where one species ends and another begins; such line-drawing problems are often taken to be the decisive reason for thinking that essentialism is untenable. However, according to the view of essentialism I suggest, this familiar objection is not fatal to essentialism. It is rather the essentialist's use of what I call the natural state model for explaining variation which clashes with evolutionary theory. This model implemented the essentialist's requirement that properties of populations be defined in terms of properties of member organisms. Requiring such constituent definitions is reductionistic in spirit; additionally, evolutionary theory shows that such definitions are not available, and, moreover, that they are not needed to legitimize population-level concepts. Population thinking involves the thesis that population concepts may be legitimized by showing their connections with each other, even when they are not reducible to concepts applying at lower levels of organization. In the paper, I develop these points by describing Aristotle's ideas on the origins of biological variation; they are a classic formulation of the natural state model. I also describe how the development of statistical ideas in the 19th century involved an abandoning of the natural state model. 1. Introduction. Philosophers have tended to discuss essentialism as if it were a global doctrine-a philosophy which, for some uniform reason, is to be adopted by all the sciences, or by none of them. Popper (1972) has taken a negative global view because he sees essentialism as a major obstacle to scientific rationality. And Quine (1953b), (1960), for a combination of semantical and epistemological reasons, likewise wishes to banish essentialism from the whole of scientific discourse. More recently, however, Putnam (1975) and Kripke (1972) have advocated essentialist doctrines and have claimed that it is the task of each science to investigate the essential properties of its constitutive natural kinds. *Received April 1979; revised December 1979. tSuggestions made by William Coleman, James Crow, Joan Kung, David Hull, Geoffrey Joseph, Steven Kimbrough, Richard Lewontin, Ernst Mayr, Terrence Penner, William Provine, Robert Stauffer, Dennis Stampe and Victor Hilts helped me consider- ably in writing this paper. Philosophy of Science, 47 (1980) pp. 350-383. Copyright ? 1980 by the Philosophy of Science Association. 350 EVOLUTION, POPULATION THINKING, AND ESSENTIALISM 351 In contrast to these global viewpoints is a tradition which sees the theory of evolution as having some special relevance to essentialist doctrines within biology. Hull (1965) and Mayr (1959) are perhaps the two best known exponents of this attitude; they are local anti-es- sentialists. For Mayr, Darwin's hypothesis of evolution by natural selection was not simply a new theory, but a new kind of theory-one which discredited essentialist modes of thought within biology and replaced them with what Mayr has called "population thinking". Mayr describes essentialism as holding that ... [t]here are a limited number of fixed, unchangeable "ideas" underlying the observed variability [in nature], with the eidos (idea) being the only thing that is fixed and real, while the observed variability has no more reality than the shadows of an object on a cave wall . . . [In contrast], the populationist stresses the uniqueness of everything in the organic world. . . . All organisms and organic phenomena are composed of unique features and can be described collectively only in statistical terms. Individuals, or any kind of organic entities, form populations of which we can determine the arithmetic mean and the statistics of variation. Averages are merely statistical abstractions, only the individuals of which the population are composed have reality. The ultimate conclusions of the population thinker and of the typologist are precisely the opposite. For the typologist the type (eidos) is real and the variation an illusion, while for the populationist, the type (average) is an abstraction and only the variation is real. No two ways of looking at nature could be more different. (Mayr 1959, pp. 28-9). A contemporary biologist reading this might well conclude that essen- tialists had no scientifically respectable way of understanding the existence of variation in nature. In the absence of this, typologists managed to ignore the fact of variability by inventing some altogether mysterious and unverifiable subject matter for themselves. The notion of types and the kind of anti-empiricism that seems to accompany it, appear to bear only the most distant connection with modern conceptions of evidence and argument. But this reaction raises a question about the precise relation of evolution to essentialism. How could the specifics of a particular scientific theory have mattered much here, since the main obstacle presented by essentialist thinking was just to get people to be scientific about nature by paying attention to the evidence? The problem was to bring people down to earth by rubbing their noses in the diversity of nature. Viewed in this 352 ELLIOTT SOBER way, Mayr's position does not look much like a form of local anti-essentialism. Other perplexities arise when a contemporary biologist tries to understand Mayr's idea of population thinking as applying to his or her own activity. If "only the individuals of which the population are composed have reality," it would appear that much of population biology has its head in the clouds. The Lotke-Volterra equations, for example, describe the interactions of predator and preypopulations. Presumably, population thinking, properly so called, must allow that there is something real over and above individual organisms. Population thinking countenances organisms and populations; typological thinking grants that both organisms and types exist. Neither embodies a resolute and ontologically austere focus on individual organisms alone. That way lies nominalism, which Mayr (1969) himself rejects. Another issue that arises from Mayr's conception of typological and population thinking is that of how we are to understand his distinction between "reality" and "abstraction." One natural way of taking this distinction is simply to understand reality as meaning existence. But presumably no population thinker will deny that there are such things as averages. If there are groups of individuals, then there are numerous properties that those groups possess. The average fecundity within a population is no more a property which we invent by "mere abstraction" than is the fecundity of individual organisms. Individual and group properties are equally "out there" to be discov- ered. And similarly, it is unclear how one could suggest that typologists held that variability is unreal; surely the historical record shows that typologists realized that differences between individuals exist. How, then, are we to understand the difference between essentialism and population thinking in terms of what each holds to be "real" about biological reality? Answering these questions about the difference between essentialist and population modes of thought will be the main purpose of this paper. How did essentialists propose to account for variability in nature? How did evolutionary theory undermine the explanatory strategy that they pursued? In what way does post-Darwinian biology embody a novel conception of variability? How has population thinking transformed our conception of what is real? The form of local anti-essentialism which I will propound in what follows will be congenial to many of Mayr's views. In one sense, then, our task will be to explicate and explain Mayr's insight that the shift from essentialist to populationist modes of thinking constituted a shift in the concept of biological reality. However, I will try to show why essentialism was a manifestly scientific working hypothesis. Typologists did not EVOLUTION, POPULATION THINKING, AND ESSENTIALISM 353 close their eyes to variation but rather tried to explain it in a particular way. And the failure of their explanatory strategy depends on details of evolutionary theory in ways which have not been much recognized.1 The approach to these questions will be somewhat historical. Essentialism about species is today a dead issue, not because there is no conceivable way to defend it, but because the way in which it was defended by biologists was thoroughly discredited. At first glance, rejecting a metaphysics or a scientific research program because one of its formulations is mistaken may appear to be fallacious. But more careful attention vindicates this pattern of evaluation. It is pie-in-the-sky metaphysics and science to hold on to some guiding principle simply because it is possible that there might be some substantive formulation and development of it. Thus, Newtonianism, guided by the maxim that physical phenomena can be accounted for in terms of matter in motion, would have been rejected were it not for the success of particular Newtonian explanations. One evaluates regulative principles by the way in which they regulate the actual theories of scientists. At the same time, I will try in what follows to identify precisely what it is in essentialism and in evolutionary theory that makes the former a victim of the latter. It is an open question to what degree the source of this incompatibility struck working biologists as central. As I will argue at the end of this section, one diagnosis of the situation which seems to have been historically important is much less decisive than has been supposed. The essentialist's method of explaining variability, I will argue, was coherently formulated in Aristotle, and was applied by Aristotle in both his biology and in his physics. 17th and 18th century biologists, whether they argued for evolution or against it, made use of Aristotle's Natural State Model. And to this day, the model has not been refuted in mechanics. Within contemporary biology, however, the model met with less success. 20th century population genetics shows that the model cannot be applied in the way that the essentialist requires. But the Natural State Model is not wholly without a home in contemporary biology; in fact, the way in which it finds an application there highlights some salient facts about what population thinking amounts to. An essentialist view of a given species is committed to there being some property which all and only the members of that species possess. 'Mayr (1963) has argued additionally that essentialist errors continue to be made in population biology in the form of the distortions of "bean-bag genetics." The assumption that the fitness of single genes is independent of their genetic context is and has been known to be mistaken; but how this simplifying assumption is essentialist in character is obscure to me. [ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ] |
||||
Wszelkie Prawa Zastrzeżone! Oto smutna prawda: cierpienie uszlachetnia. Design by SZABLONY.maniak.pl. | |||||